In probability theory, a probability space or a probability triple is a mathematical construct that models a real-world process (or "experiment") consisting of states that occur randomly. A probability space is constructed with a specific kind of situation or experiment in mind. One proposes that each time a situation of that kind arises, the set of possible outcomes is the same and the probability levels are also the same.
A probability space consists of three parts:
An outcome is the result of a single execution of the model. Since individual outcomes might be of little practical use, more complex events are used to characterize groups of outcomes. The collection of all such events is a σ-algebra . Finally, there is a need to to specify each event's likelihood of happening. This is done this using the probability measure function, P. These three components together constitute the probability space. A probability space is characterized as a “triple” because it has three components.
Once the probability space is established, it is assumed that “nature” makes its move and selects a single outcome, ω, from the sample space Ω. Then all the events in that contain the selected outcome ω (recall that each event is a subset of Ω) are said to “have occurred”. The selection performed by nature is done in such a way that if the experiment were to be repeated an infinite number of times, the relative frequencies of occurrence of each of the events would coincide with the probabilities prescribed by the function P.
The prominent Soviet mathematician Andrey Kolmogorov introduced the notion of probability space, together with other axioms of probability, in the 1930s. Nowadays alternative approaches for axiomatization of probability theory exist; see “Algebra of random variables”, for example.
This article is concerned with the mathematics of manipulating probabilities. The article probability interpretations outlines several alternative views of what "probability" means and how it should be interpreted. In addition, there have been attempts to construct theories for quantities that are notionally similar to probabilities but do not obey all their rules; see, for example, Free probability, Possibility theory, Negative probability and Quantum probability.
Contents |
A probability space presents a model for a particular class of real-world situations. As with other models, its author ultimately defines which elements Ω, , and P will contain.
Not every subset of the sample space Ω must necessarily be considered an event: Some of the subsets are simply not of interest, others cannot be “measured”. This is not so obvious in a case like a coin toss. In a different example, one could consider javelin throw lengths, where the events typically are intervals like "between 60 and 65 meters" and unions of such intervals, but not "irrational numbers between 60 and 65 meters"
In short, a probability space is a measure space such that the measure of the whole space is equal to one.
The expanded definition is following: a probability space is a triple consisting of:
Discrete probability theory needs only at most countable sample spaces Ω, which makes the foundations much less technical. Probabilities can be ascribed to points of Ω by the probability mass function p: Ω→[0,1] such that ∑ω∈Ω p(ω) = 1. All subsets of Ω can be treated as events (thus, = 2Ω is the power set). The probability measure takes the simple form
The greatest σ-algebra = 2Ω describes the complete information. In general, a σ-algebra ⊆ 2Ω corresponds to a finite or countable partition Ω = B1 ⊔ B2 ⊔ …, the general form of an event A ∈ being A = Bk1 ⊔ Bk2 ⊔ … (here ⊔ means the disjoint union.) See also the examples.
The case p(ω) = 0 is permitted by the definition, but rarely used, since such ω can safely be excluded from the sample space.
If Ω is uncountable, still, it may happen that p(ω) ≠ 0 for some ω; such ω are called atoms. They are an at most countable (maybe, empty) set, whose probability is the sum of probabilities of all atoms. If this sum is equal to 1 then all other points can safely be excluded from the sample space, returning us to the discrete case. Otherwise, if the sum of probabilities of all atoms is less than 1 (maybe 0), then the probability space decomposes into a discrete (atomic) part (maybe empty) and a non-atomic part.
If p(ω) = 0 for all ω∈Ω then equation (∗) fails: the probability of a set is not the sum over its elements, which makes the theory much more technical. Initially the probabilities are ascribed to some “generator” sets (see the examples). Then a limiting procedure allows to ascribe probabilities to sets that are limits of sequences of generator sets, or limits of limits, and so on. All these sets are the σ-algebra . For technical details see Caratheodory’s extension theorem. Sets belonging to are called measurable. In general they are much more complicated than generator sets, but much better than non-measurable sets.
If the experiment consists of just one flip of a perfect coin, then the outcomes are either heads or tails: Ω = {H, T}. The σ-algebra = 2Ω contains 2² = 4 events, namely: {H} – “heads”, {T} – “tails”, {} – “neither heads nor tails”, and {H,T} – “either heads or tails”. So, = {{}, {H}, {T}, {H,T}}. There is a fifty percent chance of tossing heads, and fifty percent for tails. Thus the probability measure in this example is P({}) = 0, P({H}) = 0.5, P({T}) = 0.5, P({H,T}) = 1.
The fair coin is tossed three times. There are 8 possible outcomes: Ω = {HHH, HHT, HTH, HTT, THH, THT, TTH, TTT} (here “HTH” for example means that first time the coin landed heads, the second time tails, and the last time heads again). The complete information is described by the σ-algebra = 2Ω of 28 = 256 events, where each of the events is a subset of Ω.
Alice knows the outcome of the second toss only. Thus her incomplete information is described by the partition Ω = A1 ⊔ A2 = {HHH, HHT, THH, THT} ⊔ {HTH, HTT, TTH, TTT}, and the corresponding σ-algebra Alice = {{}, A1, A2, Ω}. Brian knows only the total number of tails. His partition contains four parts: Ω = B0 ⊔ B1 ⊔ B2 ⊔ B3 = {HHH} ⊔ {HHT, HTH, THH} ⊔ {TTH, THT, HTT} ⊔ {TTT}; accordingly, his σ-algebra Brian contains 24 = 16 events.
The two σ-algebras are incomparable: neither Alice ⊆ Brian nor Brian ⊆ Alice; both are sub-σ-algebras of 2Ω.
If 100 voters are to be drawn randomly from among all voters in California and asked whom they will vote for governor, then the set of all sequences of 100 Californian voters would be the sample space Ω. We assume that sampling without replacement is used: only sequences of 100 different voters are allowed. For simplicity an ordered sample is considered, that is a sequence {Alice, Brian} is different from {Brian, Alice}. We also take for granted that each potential voter knows exactly his future choice, that is he/she doesn’t choose randomly.
Alice knows only whether or not Arnold Schwarzenegger has received at least 60 votes. Her incomplete information is described by the σ-algebra Alice that contains: (1) the set of all sequences in Ω where at least 60 people vote for Schwarzenegger; (2) the set of all sequences where fewer than 60 vote for Schwarzenegger; (3) the whole sample space Ω; and (4) the empty set ∅.
Brian knows the exact number of voters who are going to vote for Schwarzenegger. His incomplete information is described by the corresponding partition Ω = B0 ⊔ B1 … ⊔ B100 (though some of these sets may be empty, depending on the Californian voters…) and the σ-algebra Brian consists of 2101 events.
In this case Alice’s σ-algebra is a subset of Brian’s: Alice ⊂ Brian. The Brian’s σ-algebra is in turn the subset of the much larger “complete information” σ-algebra 2Ω consisting of 2n(n−1)…(n−99) events, where n is the number of all potential voters in California.
A number between 0 and 1 is chosen at random, uniformly. Here Ω = [0,1], is the σ-algebra of Borel sets on Ω, and P is the Lebesgue measure on [0,1].
In this case the open intervals of the form (a,b), where 0<a<b<1, could be taken as the generator sets. Each such set can be ascribed the probability of P((a,b)) = (b−a), which generates the Lebesgue measure on [0,1], and the Borel σ-algebra on Ω.
A fair coin is tossed endlessly. Here one can take Ω = {0,1}∞, the set of all infinite sequences of numbers 0 and 1. Cylinder sets {(x1,x2,…)∈Ω: x1=a1, …, xn=an} may be used as the generator sets. Each such set describes an event in which the first n tosses have resulted in a fixed sequence (a1, …, an), and the rest of the sequence may be arbitrary. Each such event can be naturally given the probability of 2−n.
These two non-atomic examples are closely related: a sequence (x1,x2,…) ∈ {0,1}∞ leads to the number 2−1x1 + 2−2x2 + … ∈ [0,1]. This is not a one-to-one correspondence between {0,1}∞ and [0,1] however: it is an isomorphism modulo zero, which allows for treating the two probability spaces as two forms of the same probability space. In fact, all non-pathologic non-atomic probability spaces are the same in this sense.
Any probability distribution defines a probability measure.
A random variable X is a measurable function X: Ω→S from the sample space Ω to another measurable space S called the state space.
The notation Pr(X∈A) is a commonly used shorthand for P({ω∈Ω: X(ω)∈A}).
If Ω is countable we almost always define as the power set of Ω, i.e. = 2Ω which is trivially a σ-algebra and the biggest one we can create using Ω. We can therefore omit ℱ and just write (Ω,P) to define the probability space.
On the other hand, if Ω is uncountable and we use = 2Ω we get into trouble defining our probability measure P because is too “large”, i.e. there will often be sets to which it will be impossible to assign a unique measure, giving rise to problems like the Banach–Tarski paradox. In this case, we have to use a smaller σ-algebra , for example the Borel algebra of Ω, which is the smallest σ-algebra that makes all open sets measurable.
Kolmogorov’s definition of probability spaces gives rise to the natural concept of conditional probability. Every set A with non-zero probability (that is, P(A) > 0) defines another probability measure
on the space. This is usually pronounced as the “probability of B given A”.
For any event B such that P(B) > 0 the function Q defined by Q(A) = P(A|B) for all events A is itself a probability measure.
Two events, A and B are said to be independent if P(A∩B)=P(A)P(B).
Two random variables, X and Y, are said to be independent if any event defined in terms of X is independent of any event defined in terms of Y. Formally, they generate independent σ-algebras, where two σ-algebras G and H, which are subsets of F are said to be independent if any element of G is independent of any element of H.
Two events, A and B are said to be mutually exclusive or disjoint if P(A∩B) = 0. (This is weaker than A∩B = ∅, which is the definition of disjoint for sets).
If A and B are disjoint events, then P(A∪B) = P(A) + P(B). This extends to a (finite or countably infinite) sequence of events. However, the probability of the union of an uncountable set of events is not the sum of their probabilities. For example, if Z is a normally distributed random variable, then P(Z=x) is 0 for any x, but P(Z∈R) = 1.
The event A∩B is referred to as “A and B”, and the event A∪B as “A or B”.